翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Onustus longleyi
・ Onut
・ Onutė Narbutaitė
・ Onuxodon
・ Onuškis
・ Onuškis Manor
・ Ontogenetic depth
・ Ontogenetic parade
・ Ontogenetic realization of categorization
・ Ontogeny
・ Ontogeny (psychoanalysis)
・ Ontogeny and Phylogeny (book)
・ Ontojärvi – Nurmesjärvi
・ Ontoko Combined School
・ Ontological argument
Ontological commitment
・ Ontological hermeneutics
・ Ontological maximalism
・ Ontological security
・ Ontologism
・ Ontology
・ Ontology (information science)
・ Ontology alignment
・ Ontology chart
・ Ontology components
・ Ontology Definition MetaModel
・ Ontology double articulation
・ Ontology engineering
・ Ontology for Biomedical Investigations
・ Ontology Inference Layer


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Ontological commitment : ウィキペディア英語版
Ontological commitment
An ontological commitment refers to a relation between a language and certain objects postulated to be extant by that language. The 'existence' referred to need not be 'real', but exist only in a universe of discourse. As an example, legal systems use vocabulary referring to 'legal persons' that are collective entities that have rights. One says the legal doctrine has an ''ontological commitment'' to non-singular individuals.〔 In information systems and artificial intelligence, where an ontology refers to a specific vocabulary and a set of explicit assumptions about the meaning and usage of these words, then an ontological commitment is an agreement to use the shared vocabulary in a coherent and consistent manner within a specific context.〔 In philosophy a "theory is ontologically committed to an object only if that object occurs in ''all'' the ontologies of that theory"〔
== Background ==
The sentence “Napoleon is one of my ancestors” apparently commits us only to the existence of two individuals (i.e., Napoleon and the speaker) and a line of ancestry between them. The fact that no other people or objects are mentioned seems to limit the “commitment” of the sentence. However, it is well known that sentences of this kind cannot be interpreted in first-order logic, where individual variables stand for individual things. Instead, they must be represented in some second-order form. In ordinary language, such second-order forms use either grammatical plurals or terms such as “set of” or “group of”.
For example, the sentence involving Napoleon can be rewritten as “any group of people that includes me and the parents of each person in the group must also include Napoleon,” which is easily interpreted as a statement in second-order logic (one would naturally start by assigning a name, such as ''G'', to the group of people under consideration). Formally, collective noun forms such as “a group of people” are represented by second-order variables, or by first-order variables standing for sets (which are well-defined objects in mathematics and logic). Since these variables do not stand for individual objects, it seems we are “ontologically committed” to entities other than individuals — sets, classes, and so on. As Quine puts it,
the general adoption of class variables of quantification ushers in a theory whose laws were not in general expressible in the antecedent levels of logic. The price paid for this increased power is ontological: objects of a special and abstract kind, viz. classes, are now presupposed. Formally it is precisely in allowing quantification over class variables α, β, etc., that we assume a range of values for these variables to refer to. To be assumed as an entity is to be assumed as a value of a variable. (''Methods of Logic'' p. 228)

Another statement about individuals that appears “ontologically innocent” is the well-known Geach–Kaplan sentence: ''Some critics admire only one another.''

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Ontological commitment」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.